logo

56 pages 1 hour read

David Hume

A Treatise of Human Nature

Nonfiction | Book | Adult | Published in 1739

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Book 2, Part 1Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Book 2, Part 1 Summary

Hume explains that he considers passions or emotions to be secondary or reflective impressions, while the primary or original impressions are feelings of pain or pleasure (327). He further divides original impressions into categories. His first pair of categories are calm (sense of beauty, admiration for art) and violent (hatred, pride, grief). Hume calls these violent impressions “passions.” He then splits passions into two further categories: direct and indirect. Direct passions are the ones responding immediately to pain or pleasure, including despair, desire, aversion, fear, hope, joy, and grief. The indirect passions also derive from our feelings of pleasure and pain, but they are shaped by other factors as well. Hume lists as examples of indirect passions love, generosity, pride, ambition, vanity, humility, pity, envy, and hatred (328).

Hume begins by looking at the passions of humility and pride. Since Hume admits we cannot describe the feeling of any passion, Hume focuses on two characteristics of the passions: cause and object. The cause is what triggers the passion, like making a work of art. Also, the cause itself is the quality (what about the cause that inspires pride) and the subject (which would be the person who feels pride). Human needs and impulses cause us to be the subject of humility and pride. However, causes come from origins more complex than just the human condition—Hume calls these origins “natural” (332-33).

There are three natural origins for pride, all of which come out of our ideas and their relations. These are the association of ideas (when one idea is related to another), the association of impressions (when one passion resembles another, like anger and envy), and mutual assistance (when we feel the same passion toward both one object and a related object). When it comes to pride, pride is caused when we have an impression of pleasure from something related to us, whether something we own, something we did, or something about ourselves. As for humility, it has a similar cause. It comes about when we have a negative impression from something related to ourselves. For example, owning a beautiful house will give us pride, but if something happens to make the house ugly or disfigured, we develop humility (340).

However, Hume admits there are five limitations. First, the relation of ideas must be close in order to be the cause of pride or humility. Second, “the agreeable or disagreeable object [must] be not only closely related, but also peculiar to ourselves, or at least common to us with a few persons” (343). Third and fourth, the cause has to be related to ourselves and to outside observers and be one that is important and long-standing. Finally, general rules and custom affect our passions, including pride and humility. In other words, social rules and the culture around us have an impact on what causes our emotions.

After listing the limitations, Hume brings up three causes of pride and humility. Hume begins with vice and virtue, which he calls “the most obvious causes of these passions” (346). Either because of human nature or from our cultural upbringing, we have impressions of pleasure from virtue and impressions of pain from vice. Similarly, beauty produces pleasure and deformity provokes pain. When we feel that something about us or closely related to us is deformed or beautiful, it causes humility or pride respectively. The last cause Hume discusses is external objects. Unlike vice and virtue or beauty and deformity, Hume argues external objects do not cause pride and humility on their own. Instead, they must have a relation of causation or contiguity to something about ourselves. For example, a person with aristocratic ancestry is most likely to feel pride in it if their family is still wealthy and has owned the same land for many generations (358-59).

Hume notes we also take pride in more abstract things, like wealth or political power, or humility from poverty even if we do not have past experience of these things. Hume argues people can receive pleasure or discomfort from anticipating what they will do with power or wealth “without any dread of punishment” (363), or what they would do without either power or money. Further, Hume suggests another reason we develop humility from poverty or pride from wealth and power is because we relate our own experience to our idea of another person. For example, a wealthy person might feel pleasure and pride from comparing their situation to that of a beggar (366).

Another abstract source of pride Hume addresses is love of fame. Hume sees this as based in sympathy—the human tendency to look to the opinions and feelings of the people in our lives (367). He argues that sympathy begins when we see signs of people’s reactions to us, such as their facial expressions, and develop an idea of that person and their feelings. The closer we are to that person, the stronger our idea of their opinions and emotions. If we become close enough to the other person, we end up adopting our idea of their opinions and taking what we believe to be their opinions as our own. We are also anxious about the reactions of people who have what Hume describes as authority (possessing some kind of special personal, social, or political status). Hume suggests it is from this type of relation that we form pride or humility from the opinions, or what we assume to be the opinions, of others.

These relationships are also shaped by the type of opinion and the type of person who is the subject of that opinion. For example, a soldier will probably not care much about people’s opinion of their eloquence (372). Hume concludes by briefly considering whether or not animals can feel humility and pride. Hume states that one can observe pride in the behavior of certain animals, like the singing of nightingales and the running of horses. Not only that, but Hume argues that since animals are capable of the association of impressions, it follows they would also be capable of humility and pride.

Book 2, Part 1 Analysis

With the second book of A Treatise of Human Nature, Hume moves on from the question of how we form our knowledge of the world to how we form emotions. Hume uses the term “passions,” although technically passions only refer to what Hume calls the violent passions. However, since most of Hume’s discussion of emotions throughout A Treatise of Human Nature talks about the violent impressions, Hume’s concept of passions is basically the same as emotions.

Another shift in Hume’s focus is that he goes from talking about how impressions and ideas develop in the mind of each individual to how the passions are linked to social and interpersonal relationships between people. Part of it is that pride and humility is caused by a relation of ideas. For example, we might feel pride because we have a strong, athletic body. Hume would say we take pleasure in that quality of ourself, but we also associate it with others and how they react to us. Further, it is sympathy—our habit of examining and reacting to the feelings of other people—that is a major reason for our passions, especially pride and humility. Our athleticism gives us pride because we can sense or hear the admiration and attraction of others, and that gives us pleasure. For the same reasons, we might feel humility—a term Hume uses to describe what we might actually call shame or embarrassment. For example, if we lose a job we actually liked having and which paid well, it is a blow to us because it makes us doubt our own idea of our worth and ability, which naturally causes us pain. It may also cause us discomfort because we fear this will cause us to become impoverished in the future, even if we have had no real past experience of poverty.

Through our sympathy, we also take in the feelings of those close to us and even people we do not know well, and that might increase our humility as we feel their pity or fear that they think less of us. This sets up Hume’s arguments about Passions and Reason, namely his argument that the passions do not get in the way of reason (461-65). We might exaggerate in our minds how much people pity us for losing our job or how attracted people are to us because of our fit body, but Hume would see these feelings as rational reactions. After all, they are based on our experience and on our own understanding of the relations and opinions of those around us.

As Hume would argue as part of his usual stance in Empiricism Versus Rationalism, passions like humility and pride are wired in us along with our sensations of pain and pleasure. Later in A Treatise of Human Nature, Hume will show that he views pain and pleasure, the passions, and our senses of vices and virtues as all deeply interconnected. For Hume, even something abstract or based in our imagination, like our plan for the future, is associated with our experience of pain and pleasure. We might feel pleasure at imagining what our life will be like after we graduate from medical school and become a successful doctor, for instance, which would encourage feelings of pride. In Hume’s philosophy, even something as intangible as our fantasies of the future are rooted in our senses and feelings of pleasure and pain.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text