logo

57 pages 1 hour read

Immanuel Kant

Critique of Pure Reason

Nonfiction | Book | Adult | Published in 1781

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Part I: “Transcendental Aesthetic”Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Transcendental Doctrine of Elements

Part I: Transcendental Aesthetic: Introduction Summary

As Kant explained in the introduction, The Critique of Pure Reason is composed of two overarching components: the Transcendental Doctrine of Elements and the Transcendental Doctrine of Method. He begins with the “Doctrine of Elements,” which is also subdivided into two main parts: the Transcendental Aesthetic and the Transcendental Logic. His first order of business is the “Aesthetic,” a term that Kant uses to describe something more technical than the study of artistic judgments. The transcendental aesthetic is “a science of all principles of a priori sensibility” (73). Kant seeks to understand the limits of human cognition.

Cognition of objects takes two forms: sensibility and understanding. While understanding deals with objects as they are thought, sensibility deals with objects as they are given to the mind (put differently, appearances). Kant writes, “intuition is that by which a cognition refers to objects directly” (71). The intuitions of sensibility are designated empirical intuitions. Since the objects of thought are originally based upon the experience of objects given to the mind by sensibility, empirical intuition forms the basis of all possible cognition. Coming to grips with its nature is of the utmost importance for the outset of the critical project. If Kant seeks a science of a priori sensibility, then he must understand the nature of empirical intuition.

Kant makes a distinction between the matter, or stuff, of sensation, and the form of sensation. The form is that which brings the sensations of objects into ordered relations. As such, the form cannot be in the sensations themselves. Instead, form is supplied by the mind prior to any given sensation. An intuition of the pure forms of sensibility abstracts from all the stuff supplied by sensations. Determining and understanding these pure forms is the business of the transcendental aesthetic because it seeks the necessary conditions for the possibility of sensation. The pure forms of intuition are these necessary conditions. 

Part I: Transcendental Aesthetic, Section I: Space Summary

There are two pure forms of intuition: space and time. Space is the outer sense of intuition whereas inner experience is constituted by the passage of time. Kant writes that “space is not an empirical concept that has been abstracted from outer experience” (77). On the contrary, space is a necessary condition for the possibility of outer experience. As such, it cannot be situated in outer experience but must be brought to it. In other words, it is a subjective condition, not an objective condition, of outer experience. Despite this, the intuition of space is still a universally necessary (transcendental) subjective condition. It is required for all human cognition in every possible circumstance. Unlike taste and color, which are contingent and differ from individual to individual, space is one and the same for all. There is only one space, though it can be arbitrarily divided into parts. We present it as “an infinite given magnitude” (79). Kant seeks to provide an “transcendental exposition” of space by which he hopes to show how synthetic a priori propositions can follow based on the concept. Kant uses geometry as an example. Geometry is made possible because of this explication of space as a transcendental condition for outer experience.

Mathematical/geometrical propositions are deductively valid, meaning that they are always true in all cases. This is not the result of empirical observation but is necessary a priori. The a priori determination of space as a transcendental condition for outer sense, which requires, for instance, three dimensionality, provides an explanation that makes the possibility of geometry understandable. So, while space is empirically real, in that it pertains to all outer experiences, it is, more fundamentally, “transcendentally ideal” (82). The external objects we encounter in space are only appearances, or presentations, that are the result of our cognitive capacity of sensibility. The thing behind the appearance, or “thing in itself,” can never directly be the object of experience (84). 

Part I: Transcendental Aesthetic, Section II: Time Summary

The metaphysical exposition of time parallels the same exposition of space. However, whereas the concept of space refers to intuition of outer experience, the concept of time refers to intuition of inner experience, or inner sense. Like space, time is not an empirical concept. It is not grounded in experience but is, rather, the ground of experience. In other words, “time is a necessary presentation that underlies all intuitions” (86). Apodeictic principles, those that are beyond dispute, are derivable from time when understood as an “inner sense.” The principle that time proceeds sequentially (not simultaneously) is one such principle. It cannot be derived from experience but must be the result of the nature of time itself. Time is present to consciousness as unlimited. It is unlimited sequentiality through which all determinate portions of time are parceled.

Just as the transcendental exposition of the concept of space elucidated the possibility of geometry, the transcendental exposition of time “explains the possibility of all that synthetic a priori cognition which is set forth by the–quite fertile–general theory of motion” (87). Also, analogously to the concept of space, time is not merely empirically real but is (more fundamentally) transcendentally ideal. While it holds with objective certainty for all possible experience (making it empirically real), at base it is a formal, subjective condition of the human mind. Kant writes that we cannot claim that time has any absolute reality. In abstraction from our capacity for sensibility, Kant says, “time is nothing” (90). Time is even more general to human experience than space insofar as it is the “inner intuition” of sensibility, and outer intuition must pass through inner intuition. In short, all experience is unavoidably placed in time. Time also applies to outer sense, or intuition constituted by space.

According to Kant, the transcendental aesthetic is a completed science when it understands space and time. There cannot be any more elements because “all other concepts belonging to sensibility presuppose something empirical” (93). Transcendental conditions are necessarily a priori metaphysical conditions and therefore nonempirical.

Part I: Transcendental Aesthetic, Section II: General Comments Summary

Kant completes his engagement with the transcendental aesthetic. He concludes that we cannot know objects as they are independent of our perception. We cannot abstract from our sensible intuitions of space and time. “Even if,” Kant writes, “we were able to see through that appearance and to its very bottom” we would still not have knowledge of the object as it is itself, apart from our intuition of it (96). This object beyond appearance is known as the transcendental object. It must exist for the possibility of experience, but it is not ever presented within that experience. The pure intuitions of space and time constitute the formal parameters of sensibility through which we receive the objects of experience. Kant writes “our kind of intuition is called sensible because it is not original” (103). Therefore, the activity of our spatial intuition is determined through the existence of objects external to us. Even if we can only be aware of these objects through the way they appear to us, we know that these appearances are something external to us. Appearances are not illusions. The objects that are sensed, or received, are external to the mind via the outer sense of space. Inner sense, or time, is internal to the mind, but nevertheless still only presents objects as appearance. Even the appearance of the self, the I (the subject), is present merely as an appearance: “The consciousness of oneself (apperception) is the simple presentation of the I” (100). Our intuition of ourselves is merely sensible and therefore no different from any other intuition. Having acquired knowledge of the nature of space and time, Kant writes that he has made headway on answering the question regarding the possibility of synthetic a priori propositions, which is the fundamental problem to be answered for transcendental philosophy. 

Part I: “Transcendental Aesthetic” Analysis

Kant’s work in the “Transcendental Aesthetic” was revolutionary for the philosophy of his day. Before Kant made space a transcendental condition of the perception of external objects, the main theories on space were those of Isaac Newton and Gottfried Leibniz. Newton believed that space was an absolute magnitude within which things existed. Leibniz, on the other hand, believed space was the result of the relations between objects. Kant’s transcendental account views both positions as dogmatic.

Kant staked new ground in an essential 18th century debate about the nature of space and time. Kant’s move is to make space and time intuitions of the human mind, formal constraints under which the world appears to us. Based on this view, it becomes impossible to coherently think about space and time as they exist independent of the human mind. In fact, space and time do not exist independent of the human mind, and we really cannot say anything about what does, especially since experience is determined by space and time. Kant writes, “[I]f we annul ourselves as subject, or even annul only the subjective character of the senses generally, then this entire character of objects and all their relations in space and time–indeed, even space and time themselves–would vanish” (94).

For Kant, when investigating what we can know about the world, the philosopher must investigate the nature of her own mind, especially in its most basic elements. Though space and time are both empirically real because they are experienced, they are more essentially transcendental ideals, because they form the conditions for the possibility of experience. This means that Kant is a transcendental idealist. In this context, an idealist is not someone who pursues ideals or goals with zealous optimism, but rather someone who believes that the nature of experience is, in some important sense, constituted by the human mind.

For Kant, space and time are elements of his idealism. However, this should not be taken to mean that the appearances of objects are invented spontaneously by the mind. This is especially evident in the case of space, which is the sensible intuition of objects external to the mind. However, even if they were internal to the mind, as they are with time, they would not be illusions. Kant explains that this is because these are presentations as they are “actually given” (101). The mind receives these presentations through its pure forms of intuition. They are not tricks that the mind plays on itself.

The “Transcendental Aesthetic” is, then, the first part of Kant’s explication of the elements of the human mind, and it contains doctrines of space and time, the forms of inner and outer sensibility. Sensibility may concern the way the mind receives (rather than produces) the objects of its world, but it is still essentially of the mind. It is the first portion of Kant’s project of transcendental idealism. Rather than making any claims about the nature of the world as it is, Kant is only concerned with describing and understanding the mind’s side of the story. In his view, it is the only side about which we can have direct knowledge. The aesthetic of sensibility, though, is only half of the story, and it must be synthesized with the logic of understanding to yield human experience.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text