57 pages • 1 hour read
Immanuel KantA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
Summary
Chapter Summaries & Analyses
Prefaces and Introduction
Part I: “Transcendental Aesthetic”
Part II: “Transcendental Logic,” Book I, Chapter I
Part II: “Transcendental Logic,” Book I, Chapter II
Part II: “Transcendental Logic,” Book II, Chapters I-II
Part II: “Transcendental Logic,” Book II, Chapter III
Part II: “Transcendental Logic,” Division II, Books I-II, Chapter I
Part II: “Transcendental Logic,” Division II, Book II, Chapter II
Part II: “Transcendental Logic,” Division II, Book II, Chapter III
Transcendental Doctrine of the Method
Key Figures
Themes
Index of Terms
Important Quotes
Essay Topics
Further Reading & Resources
Tools
The “Transcendental Analytic” has been the study of the nature of understanding, especially its categories and principles. Before turning his attention to the faculty of reason in the “Transcendental Dialectic,” Kant thinks it is necessary to include a couple of addenda.
The first is an extended discussion on the distinction between phenomena and noumena, which requests a distinction between a transcendental concept and an empirical concept. Transcendental concepts refer to objects as they supposedly exist “in themselves,” that is, beyond our experience of them. Empirical concepts are always of objects as they appear, “i.e., to objects of a possible experience” (305). Kant attempts to prove that the categories of the understanding are always only of empirical use. The objects of transcendental concepts are noumena and the objects of empirical concepts are phenomena. Kant writes that “intellectual intuition” would be necessary to perceive objects beyond the way in which they appear to us in sensible intuition. This is not something that the mind can do, though, and so we can never have an experience of an object that is not empirical.
After this, Kant provides an appendix on “The Amphiboly of Concepts of Reflection.” An amphiboly is an ambiguity that results from the way in which words are grammatically constructed. Kant seeks to clarify the issue by developing the notion of transcendental deliberation, which is a process in which the mind reflects on a given concept and decides whether they belong to understanding or sensible intuition. It is only by holding concepts to the light of these kinds of cognition that it can be decided wherein they reside. The potential ways in which concepts of the mind are comparable to one another are fourfold:
1. Sameness and Difference
2. Agreement and Conflict
3. Intrinsic and Extrinsic
4. Matter and Form
Kant provides brief accounts of each of these in relation to his notion of transcendental deliberation. Then he provides an extended commentary on the amphiboly in which he criticizes Leibniz and Locke for making opposite mistakes in reasoning about this issue because neither properly distinguished sensibility nor understanding through transcendental deliberation. Kant criticizes the notion of an intellectual object, i.e., an object divorced from sensible experience. “Hence the concept of the noumenon,” he writes, “is not the concept of an object; rather, it is the problem” (342). The problem of the noumenon resides in the limits of our abilities in empirical intuition and whether there are objects that exist beyond the threshold of sensible experience. However, this problem is one that must remain unresolved.
The importance of the distinction between the realm of appearances (phenomena) and the realm of “things in themselves” (noumena) is difficult to underestimate. Kant’s project requires a meaningful conceptual separation of the understanding from reason. He writes, “if the understanding cannot distinguish whether or not certain questions lie within its horizon, then it can never be sure of its claims and its possessions; rather, it must then count on receiving a multitude of embarrassing rebukes when (as is unavoidable) it keeps overstepping the bounds of its domain and stray into delusion and deception” (305). Therefore, it is necessary to comprehend the boundaries of the understanding. The previous section systematically dealt with its positive principles, but with the concept of the noumena Kant comes up to the boundary and attempts to explain how we are to think about what lies beyond. In short, we can’t think about them except as a problem.
One could say that categories of the understanding reside beyond experience as formal conditions of experience and that their existence is possible beyond their application to experience. Kant would disagree. Whereas categories of understanding might be logically possible outside of their empirical application, they can never be proven to be really possible except through this reference to experience. The simple fact that something is not logically impossible does not mean that it could ever actually exist. For this, a possible intuition is necessary. Experience is the point of contact for any determination of the real possibility of any concept of the understanding. This means, in turn, that all that we can understand is phenomena, or objects as they appear in experience. The understanding must remain silent regarding the existence of any objects beyond their appearance in experience. The things beyond appearance, the noumena, cannot be intuited, and therefore we can never prove that they really exist. In fact, their existence is merely problematic. In other words, “the concept of a noumenon is, therefore, only a boundary concept serving to limit the pretension of sensibility, and hence is only of negative use” (319).
The reason Kant invokes the notion of a transcendental deliberation in the following section, the “Amphiboly of Concepts of Reflection,” is also related to the general concern regarding classification and boundaries. To really understand the kinds of cognition thus far explored in the book (i.e., sensible intuition and pure understanding), it is important to know how to classify the presentations of the mind as referring to one or the other. Doing so should clarify what the understanding is capable of and why it is necessary that it always attaches itself to sensible intuition for the possible cognition of an object.
Kant explains: “Thought is not, indeed, in itself a product of the senses, and is to that extent also not limited by them; but it does not therefore have its own and pure use forthwith, without the assistance of sensibility since it is then without an object” (342). The understanding (and, as we will see, reason) extends beyond mere sensibility. We can think a priori, or before any application to sense experience, but none of these thoughts have any material (or object) without reference to experience.
For example, we can think about elephants in various situations without thinking about any actual elephant or any real-world event, but we would never have the object of thought “elephant” without some original exposure in sensible intuition to the animal. More technically, we can, for example, think about possibility or causality without reference to any actual possible thing or causal event, but we have no access to these principles without objects of experience.
By Immanuel Kant