37 pages • 1 hour read
Friedrich NietzscheA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
Drawing on a quotation from Goethe in which the writer and statesman says he has “an obscure inkling of his error,” Nietzsche claims that the historical focus of contemporary education produces skepticism in “more highly developed historical men” (49). Nietzsche proceeds to argue that this focus on history is derived from Christian theological scholarship:
Does not this paralyzing belief in an already withering mankind rather harbour the misunderstanding, inherited from the Middle Ages, of a Christian theological conception, the thought that the end of the world is near, of the fearfully expected judgment? (49).
Nietzsche is also critical of the notion that modernity is the culmination of history, because this apocalyptic mentality “is hostile toward all new planting” (49).
Furthermore, Nietzsche argues, judgment-orientated Christian theology has “dispersed itself into the skeptical consciousness” (50). This kind of history “makes its servants passive and retrospective” (50). Nietzsche goes as far as to state: “in this sense we still live in the Middle Ages and history is still a disguised theology” (50). Nietzsche turns to the idea of a “new age,” arguing that such an era must neutralize the “problem” of history in establishing itself.
Next, Nietzsche shows the influence of Hegelian thought on the contemporary “idolatry of the factual” (51). Hegel’s conceptualization of God, Nietzsche argues, privileges Hegel’s own experience, implying that what follows is “redundant” (52). Nietzsche criticizes the passivity with which his contemporaries “bow” before history’s power. There is an inconsistency in the conception that religion is extinct, ascribing a religious fervor to the modern preoccupation with history.
In Chapter 8, Nietzsche distinguishes between the “historical education” prevalent in his own time, and a truly “historical” individual, people, or epoch. The latter form of history is defined as being “strong, that is, in deeds and works” (48), which pertains to the “monumental” kind of history he has defined in the text’s early chapters. Nietzsche likens the historical sensibility in Chapter 8 to a cultural “fever” (50). He advocates for the German people ceasing to students of an era of “fading antiquity” and embracing an unhistorical age, characterized by an “unspeakably rich” life. In the present historically-saturated culture, Nietzsche argues, modern people are “living memories.”
In the contemporary deification of success, Nietzsche divines the influence of Hegelian philosophy, in which the idea, or “mind” is the ultimate. He calls this reification of the events of history “the tyranny of the actual” (54). The chapter closes by aligning forgetting and living, with the optimistic pronouncement that “there is a way of living which will erase this from memory” (54).
By Friedrich Nietzsche