31 pages • 1 hour read
Karl Marx, Friedrich EngelsA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
A brief preamble outlines Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels’ reasons for writing the Manifesto. Various European powers have united against the “spectre” of communism, which is, to the authors, an anxiety response to the movement. This response proves that communism is a force to be reckoned with and that it is high time for Communists to lay out their philosophy and game plan.
Part 1, “Bourgeois and Proletarians,” centers on the authors’ social and political theories regarding Europe’s newly industrialized society. Class struggle has been a mainstay throughout history, they argue, but before industrialization, inequality existed on a spectrum; stages of gradation separated the most powerful citizens from the most powerless. For example, in ancient Rome, the noble class were the most powerful members of society, followed by knights, plebeians, and slaves. Marx and Engels distinguish the current age, “the bourgeoisie,” by its simplification of this spectrum. A widening inequality gap eroded the middle classes, leaving only two parties in direct conflict with each other: the ruler class (the bourgeoisie) and the working class (the proletariat).
This change was brought about by two major factors: globalization and industrialization. 16th and 17th century European colonization of the Americas and Asia created a new, interconnected world market, but the demands of this market could not be met by the older, more localized modes of production, like guilds, in the feudal system. Steam-powered factory machinery was invented, revolutionizing the way goods were produced and launching the owners of this new means of production, the bourgeoisie, into positions of incredible power.
The power of the bourgeoisie grew, and soon, the state itself (i.e. the government) functioned primarily to protect their interests: “The executive of the modern State is but a committee for managing the common affairs of the whole bourgeoisie” (12). As a result, the bourgeoisie achieved not only class supremacy, but political supremacy, which Marx posits are fundamentally interconnected.
To Marx, bourgeois prioritization of free trade and profit had dire social ramifications. It reduced the worth of a person to what he or she can produce. Previously, religious and social customs hid the exploitation of the lower classes behind a veneer of civility; later, egotism and greed reigned supreme, to the detriment of the workers (12).
The bourgeois system is defined, the authors argue, by its rapacious nature. Capitalism relies on a constantly changing and expanding market to thrive. Its relentless expansion erodes the boundaries between countries, forcing new areas to submit to its way of life. Poorer countries cannot resist conversion and survive; bourgeois imperialism relies not on military might, but economic conquest as “the cheap prices of its commodities are the heavy artillery” (14). Unmanageable overproduction caused severe economic crises in Europe in the 1830s and 40s, a fact Marx uses while arguing that the bourgeoisie can no longer control expansion and growth.
Ultimately, the system’s weakness is its dependence on the exploitation of a downtrodden working class, known as the proletariat. The working class has been reduced to commodities in the system, subject to the ups and downs of the market. They have become “a class of laborers who live only so long as they can find work, and who find work only so long as their labor increases capital” (15). Their role as cogs in the machine was rarely rewarding; worse, the more unappealing the job, the less the wages (15-16).
But cutthroat competition among the bourgeois themselves—and the deplorable conditions they forced on workers—drove workers to unite against them. The globalization which propelled the bourgeoisie to prominence also provided the mass transportation and communication networks necessary for workers to unite, even across geographical lines (17). As a result, as the power of the bourgeoisie grew, so too did the power of the proletariats.
Marx predicts that conflict between the bourgeoisie and proletariats will inevitably turn violent. As petty-bourgeois manufacturers and shopkeepers see their business dwindle, unable to compete with richer or more powerful competitors, they will abandon their class and side with the proletariats, who vastly outnumber the bourgeoisie. This conflict will be the tipping point: “All previous movements were movements of minorities […] The proletarian movement is the self-conscious, independent movement of the immense majority” (18). The bourgeoisie will inevitably be overthrown, Marx argues, because it has proved itself unfit to rule as their systems rely entirely on the impoverishment of others.
At the beginning of The Communist Manifesto, Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels establish communism as an outsider philosophy and its Manifesto as a reactionary, revolutionary document. 19th century European powers perceived communism simultaneously as an insubstantial force and an insidious presence; though the influence of communism was widespread at this time in history, communism was not widely understood, making the comparison of the movement to a spectre apt. In Marx and Engels’ time, “communist” was a label political opponents could use to impugn each other no matter if the politicians addressed as such had any philosophical predilection to communism. Politicians had the freedom to use the term freely because, Marx and Engels argue, a document did not yet exist which clearly stated communist philosophies. By creating the Manifesto, they aimed to establish the platform of the world’s first Marxist political party, the Communist League, founded in Brussels on June 1, 1847.
While Engels collaborated with Marx and edited much of the writing in the Manifesto, Marx is generally thought to be responsible for the development of the Manifesto’s specific brand of communism, which is now referred to as Marxism. In developing his theory of history, Marx was heavily influenced by the German philosopher Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770-1831). Hegel believed that history progressed through increasingly better stages of development, as human reason had time to work and to bring mankind closer to a utopian ideal of freedom. In Hegel’s view, history marches persistently upwards: each successive form of society is an improvement on the last, and it is impossible for one stage to slide backwards into the former.
Marx generally agreed with Hegel’s theory of history. He accepted that shifts must take place from 1) tribalism (a means of production owned and shared by individuals whose relationships with each other are based on kinship) to 2) slave-owning (a means of production and land managed and owned by a master) to 3) feudalism (a means of production characterized by aristocratic rule) to 4) a bourgeois-run capitalist society (characterized by a powerful but oppressive middle class) to 5) a revolution of the proletariat (the rise of the working man and true equality). Each step must be followed by the next, and each stage represents a general improvement in the human condition. Societies cannot skip over a stage; each is necessary to the development of humanity as a whole.
Marx’s application of Hegelian philosophy to his writing enabled him and Engels to identify class struggle as the through line for human history. Marx’s historical stages are not determined by a society’s morals, legal priorities, or religion—in fact, to Marx, religion is a negative force which is often used to veil or excuse exploitation. For Marx, the single most important factor in determining historical progress is the society’s economic system. He was especially interested in identifying which class owns the means of production. For Marx, class struggle is the key to understanding history; therefore, economics must be spotlighted, because classes rise from the economic structures of their societies.
Armed with this system of Hegelian philosophy—and inspired by Charles Darwin, who posited that reason can be used to determine natural law—Marx applied reason to the study of human history. He traced the movement of historical epochs, and, notably, he predicted that the conflict between the bourgeoisie and the proletariat would be the final class conflict. Thanks to a widening inequality gap, the exploitation of the proletariat by the bourgeoisie became obvious and religion and other social elements which had allowed exploitation to flourish in the past were destroyed by capitalism. The constant innovation and change characteristic of the bourgeois system led to unprecedented instability, and as a result, in Marx’s opinion, the proletariat revolution was not only inevitable, but very near.
By these authors