31 pages • 1 hour read
Karl Marx, Friedrich EngelsA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
Part 3 centers on three schools of socialism familiar to Marx and Engels, identifying their problems or inconsistencies and outlining why Marxism is the preferable alternative. The first category is Reactionary Socialism and its three subsets: Feudal Socialism, Petty-Bourgeois Socialism, and German, or “True” Socialism. The second category is Conservative, or Bourgeois Socialism. The third and final category is Critical-Utopian Socialism and Communism.
The first category Marx addresses is Reactionary Socialism. This type of socialism has three subsets: Feudal Socialism, Petty-Bourgeois Socialism, and German, or “True” Socialism. Feudal Socialism is the oldest form of socialism. It was set forth by the feudal aristocracy which comprised of mostly French and English nobility. These upper-class individuals styled themselves as socialists not because they hated the new bourgeois class, but rather because they recognized the inevitable by-product of the bourgeois capitalist system: angry proletariats. The aristocrats recognized that a reactionary working class who was determined to change society represented a dire threat to the noble way of life. The Feudal Socialists’ insincere pretensions to siding with the working class were a futile attempt to project solidarity, according to Marx.
Like the nobles of Feudal Socialism, the second subset of Reactionary Socialism, the Petty-Bourgeois Socialists, also feared self-annihilation. They weren’t nobles, but rather solidly middle-class artisans and guildsmen who hovered somewhere between bourgeois and proletariat (hence their name, the Petty-Bourgeois). They too recognized that the progression of the socialist agenda would eventually do away with their status entirely, and the well-to-do middle classes eventually merged with the proletariat.
To their credit, the Petty-Bourgeois Socialists, led by Sismondi, who was the head of their school in France and England, provided incisive observations about the dismal conditions of modern production. They were too intent, however, on returning the means of production to how it was before industrialization—when the middle class guild-types were thriving; more helpful would have been efforts to understand that the framework of property relations needed to be destroyed and rebuilt from the ground up (30-31).
The third subset of Reactionary Socialism, known as German, or “True” Socialism, took its cue from the French Socialists but lost something during its development. France’s socialist movement was advanced because its bourgeois class was advanced: their power was brought about quickly and decisively by the French Revolution of 1789 to 1799; the Revolution jump-started French bourgeois power by forcibly removing the aristocratic class. Thus in Marx’s eyes, France accelerated through societal stages more quickly than other areas in Europe; their bourgeois class was already at the height of its power, and as a result, French socialism developed quickly. The Germans appropriated France socialist literature, but because the German bourgeois class had barely begun to establish itself, the Germans misinterpreted French socialist arguments as a kind of theoretical exercise. They misunderstood hard-won French demands as an expression of universal human ideals (e.g. “Reason”), rather than practical advice meant to deal with very real problems (33). The result, according to Marx and Engels, was dire for the German proletariat. The noble and petty-bourgeois classes united against the German bourgeois before it could even establish itself. Because socialism could not take root until capitalism was established, this paradox stymied German socialist progress.
After addressing three facets of Reactionary Socialism, Marx turns to the second category: Conservative, or Bourgeois Socialism. This socialism was espoused by well-intentioned members of the bourgeois themselves, like “economists, philanthropists, humanitarians, improvers of the condition of the working class, [and] organizers of charity” (34). Despite their privilege, these bourgeois recognized the human rights issues that afflicted the capitalist society which made them successful. They strived to find ways to improve social conditions for all, but they were unwilling to part with the framework which empowered them. Simply put, they “want[ed] all the advantages of modern social conditions without the struggles and dangers necessarily resulting therefrom […] they wish[ed] for a bourgeois without a proletariat.” (35). Most damagingly, some bourgeois socialists sought to stigmatize revolutionary action, encouraging non-violent administrative reform. In contrast, Marx argues that only true revolution can dismantle the system (36). Ultimately, bourgeois socialists attempted to advocate for the working class, but not at the expense of losing their own advantages.
Finally, Marx addresses Critical-Utopian Socialism and Communism. This title is given to the earliest socialists of the bourgeois era, including Charles Fourier and Robert Owen. These socialists correctly predicted and identified the relationship between the bourgeoisie and the proletariats, but they did not have a complete understanding of the role of the proletariat. Rather, they understood only that the proletariat was the downtrodden class and therefore in dire need of assistance. They were less interested in the permanent triumph of the proletariat and more interested in the peaceful bettering of society for all classes—even the richest. Predictably, Marx denigrates the Critical-Utopians for being too idealistic, believing that true change could never occur without revolution (36-37).
In Part 3, Marx offers his thoughts on previous socialist texts and points out why they are not adequate. The Manifesto’s criticism of these ideologies can be boiled down to three main arguments. First, other brands of socialism do not recognize the fundamentally class-based nature of the conflict; Marx, on the other hand, is responsible for the introduction of the notion of class struggle as the source of all conflict in human history. For example, though the German socialists believed the movement embodied a triumph of the human spirit, Marx the materialist was highly resistant to the idea of abstract, “eternal” human truth. The only eternal truth, he argues, is the oppression of one section of society by another. As well, the German school portrayed the struggle of the proletariat as the struggle of the human race in general, which “emasculate[s]” the movement. To Marx, the German socialists removed the potency of the issue by stripping it of its proper context. To Marx, socialism must be rooted in real-world problems and it must attempt to give real-world solutions.
Marx’s second criticism concerns the preservation of the current class system or a desire to return to an older, even worse way of living within a society. Some socialists identify with socialism for selfish reasons; for example, the aristocratic Feudal Socialists were anti-bourgeois only because they did not want the bourgeois to antagonize the proletariat and position the proletariat against them. Others, like the Bourgeois Socialists, were more genuinely sympathetic to the proletariat and recognized the injustice of the system, but they were reluctant to give up the benefits they enjoyed under a capitalist system. They wanted to maintain the system and somehow make everyone happier. Marxism advocates for a wholescale revolution; no part of the system, he argues, can be salvaged.
Marx’s third and final argument acknowledges the refusal of other socialists to accept the necessity of violent revolution. Many other brands of socialism not only discouraged the complete dismantling of the system, but they also actively chided advocates for violent reform. Their intentions were peaceful, but their interference, Marx argues, hindered progress. To Marx, the old system must be dismantled completely to create the new, and the end will justify the means.
By these authors