63 pages • 2 hours read
Francis FukuyamaA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
The final section of The End of History and the Last Man is focused on that very proverbial last man. In the previous sections, the author demonstrated that history is unidirectional, that technological progress is essential, and that the world tends toward liberal democracies. However, liberal democracies are not without their problems, including social inequalities, homelessness, crime, and substance abuse. At the very least, the end of history could mean “the end of wars and bloody revolutions” (310). But democracy has its own discontents.
In Chapter 27, Fukuyama returns to the question of a “trans-historical standard” which he raised earlier in the book. This standard is meant to establish an ideal human being (“man as man”) against which liberal democracies could be measured (288). It remains to be seen whether liberal democracies could truly meet one’s “desire for recognition” (288). One of the key problems with establishing a safe and secure society of material abundance, according to the author, is having the pendulum swing too far in the other direction. If historic societies involved much bloodshed and cruelty, then one of the dangers of an advanced liberal democracy is the “last men.”
These last men, to use Friedrich Nietzsche’s term from Thus Spake Zarathustra, are passive and even nihilistic. For Hegel, this is the “domestication of the master” and the “metamorphosis into economic man” (333). They are more concerned with safety, security, and material well-being than risk-taking and the creative element that keeps the world going forward. Fukuyama refers to them as “men without chests” in the title of Chapter 28 to indicate that these people no longer have the passion of thymos burning in their hearts. (300). Since the “desire for recognition is the most fundamental human longing,” these last men have lost that very part of themselves that makes them truly human (288). A key “question at the end of history then amounts to a question of the future of thymos” (288).
Therefore, liberal democracies are plagued with two problems: psychologically satisfying thymos and establishing a true equality in a material and social sense. Even by a “relatively relaxed standard of equality, most existing liberal democracies do not yet fully measure up” (291). These inequalities often exist along age-old divisions like race and gender.
Fukuyama argues that liberal democracies naturally work to eliminate inequalities and give rise to the middle class. However, at the time of his writing, these inequalities were a long way from being eliminated. For example, the different standard of living for the African Americans in Detroit versus the wealthier parts of the United States is a sign that the founding principle of equality “remains to be implemented fully for many Americans in the 1990s” (291). Since it is impossible to eliminate social inequalities “even in the most perfect of liberal societies,” then there will always be “tension between the principles of liberty and equality” (292). Yet these societies are ideal, according to the author, because the end of the Cold War signaled the lack of radical solutions on the part of Leftists. However, resentment may be stronger in such societies because differences are felt more acutely.
If the Hegelian “universal and homogenous state” transformed the former slaves into their own masters, then the Nietzschean last man was a “victorious slave” (300). In this framework, Christianity is a “slave ideology,” and democracy is a “secularized form of Christianity” (301). By extension, the equality of people before God in a religious context is comparable to democratic equality in the legal context. For Nietzsche, this concept was negative because of his conviction that authentic creativity and freedom could only exist in hierarchic, aristocratic societies. According to Fukuyama, Nietzsche’s dislike of liberal democracy is extreme, but there is some truth to his assessment:
Modern-day America has managed to contrive it so that its brightest and most privileged young people produce things that are neither beautiful nor useful, such as the mountains of litigation produced by lawyers every year (309).
For Hegel, a “liberal democratic state did not constitute a synthesis of the morality of the master and the morality of the slave” (301). However, it is the “universal and homogenous state” that could give an individual the kind of recognition that he or she desires, according to the German philosopher.
Fukuyama compares Nietzsche and Hegel as opposites in this context. For Nietzsche, a proponent of social hierarchies, the egalitarianism of a democratic society creates the last men—passive humans without pride. For Hegel, it is the democratic society that offers the optimal recognition of one’s identity.
The author believes that the best and the brightest heading into business rather than more creative fields is “in the very design of democratic capitalist countries” (316). He wonders whether the amazing human feats of the past millennia amounted to the modern-day democratic politicians promising safety and security. The author suggests, therefore, that megalothymia will remain even in the most egalitarian of societies in such fields as competitive sports. The realm of politics is also one of competition and recognition because “[e]lectoral politics is a thymotic activity” (317). This form of society and government resolved “the problem of megalothymia by constraining and sublimating it through a complex series of institutional arrangements” (333).
Fukuyama provides examples to back up his argument about these harmless expressions of megalothymia. One such example is the World Cup in which people express pride in one’s team and one’s country in a non-military setting. The author suggests that “high-risk leisure activities that have no purpose but to shake the participant out of the comfort of a bourgeois existence” are another healthy way of channeling megalothymia (319). These activities range from skydiving to running marathons.
Another area of interest for Fukuyama is the relationship between people’s rights and their duties within a liberal democracy. In this dynamic, “[m]oral obligation is entirely contractual” (323). As a result, communities that are not bound by traditional ties such as religion and culture, but in this abstract way instead, display weaknesses in terms of their cohesion and the obligations for their members. For example, in the smallest unit of a community—a family—the personal interactions are often irrational. Communities are also threatened by “the pressures of the capitalist marketplace” (325).
Fukuyama argues that capitalism creates atomization and loneliness in many ways such as relocating for a job. He concludes that something significant is missing in Liberalism, and that community life “must ultimately come from a source different from liberalism itself” (326). Herein lies the danger of “becoming secure and self-absorbed last men” (328). Yet in the previous sections, the author celebrated the destruction of traditional communal ties by the individualistic Liberal ideology and argued that only benign and surface-based forms of cultural differences, such as ethnic cuisines, should remain.
Because of this danger of becoming “soft and self-absorbed,” Hegel believed that the possibility of war served as a preventative measure (329). The horrors of war allow one to develop an appropriate understanding of what is important and what is not. Fukuyama argues that there are historical examples to back this psychological theory up, such as the 1968 student protests in France. He suggests that it was “the absence of struggle” in “one of the freest and most prosperous societies on earth” that led to the unrest. (330). The author asserts that “[b]oredom with peace and prosperity” may lead to much worse consequences (330). He recalls the century of relative peace in Europe, at least when it came to major international wars, prior to World War I. To use Hegelian terminology, this transition during Modernity constitutes “the domestication of a master” (333).
Another danger to liberal democracy comes from relativism, according to the author. The belief that values are relative may undermine the values of democracy. Fukuyama argues that this is precisely what Nietzsche attempted to do when he disparaged Christianity for being egalitarian. Liberal democracy, like Christianity, is egalitarian. It no longer has to tackle megalothymia “by constraining and sublimating” it through institutional arrangement itself (333). For this reason, turning into the “last men” could pose a greater danger than believing oneself to be superior to all others in Fukuyama’s optimal societal model.
By Francis Fukuyama