53 pages • 1 hour read
Friedrich HayekA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
People have argued that economics and money are lowly affairs that should be left to government administrators, while we focus on the higher things in life. But those inspiring pursuits also have costs, and Hayek points out that a planned economy “would control the allocation of the limited means for all our ends” (126). We would be restricted even in our loftier pursuits by government.
In a free market, our choices are limited by how much others are willing to pay for things we want, and we adjust our spending accordingly. A government that controls an economy has monopoly power over our purchasing decisions, and the government’s preferences, rather than our own, would control us.
Just as important is our freedom to choose our livelihood, which also would be curtailed in a planned economy: “The person whose qualifications are not of the standard type, or whose temperament is not of the ordinary kind, will no longer be able to come to special arrangements with an employer whose dispositions will fit in with his special needs” (129). Workers, far from being respected, “would more than ever become a mere means, to be used by the authority” (130).
Many a “bitter choice” people must make in the free market would be relieved in a planned economy, but only “through having the choice made for them by others” (130). What’s more, the idea that socialism will bring about prosperity is completely unsupported in the historical record: “Yet it is this false hope as much as anything which drives us along the road to planning” (131).
Many socialist economists agree, and instead they hope that their program “will enable us to secure a more just and equitable distribution of wealth” (131). Hayek warns that such a purpose might cause “more discontent and more oppression than was ever caused by the much-abused free play of economic forces” (132).
Supporters of planning finally argue that their restrictions would certainly be no worse than what people experienced in earlier centuries. Hayek replies that the ancestral rules were generalized, hard to enforce, and otherwise left most workers free of regulation. In the more complex modern world, it wouldn’t be enough merely to control people’s economic choices, since everything else they do in life is also “dependent on someone else’s economic activities” (132). As in Nazi Germany, Western nations’ planners might even have to regulate the leisure time of their workers.
While it’s true that economic freedom gives advantages to those born to wealth or who are otherwise lucky, freedom also gives people the chance to raise their circumstances by their own efforts. This is better than “a system where it is the will of a few persons that decides who is to get what” (134).
In a planned society, the state has power that no one in a free society can possess. In a competitive economy, the power of ownership is spread out across so many players that, even for the poor, “nobody has complete power over us, that we as individuals can decide what to do with ourselves […] And who will deny that a world in which the wealthy are powerful is still a better world than one in which only the already powerful can acquire wealth?” (136)
Controlling an entire economy is so complex and daunting that most planners would rather avoid dictating all the minutiae. Since every part of an economy affects every other, any change made by planners will cause other changes, to the point where the planners must finally reach ever deeper into people’s lives in order to guide their affairs.
At this point, people will notice that the bad outcomes arrive, not from luck or circumstance, as in the old competitive market system, but from the decisions of bureaucrats. People will learn that the only real economic power is political—that what matters is not what you can produce but whom you know in the government.
Whether planners seek for perfect equality, which is simple but impractical, or merely more equality, they must still navigate the innumerable moral quandaries presented by all the competing interests of their subjects. What is a just price? What is a fair wage? How much should be produced? There is no way to answer these questions, even in a socialist marketplace. Yet the planner must try, and the answers will decide the fates of all the workers. A free people would be unlikely to put up with these conditions.
Worse, coalitions that influence the planners will fight among themselves over which set of values should dictate the system of allocation. Ultimately, this decision will be arbitrary: “It is not rational conviction but the acceptance of a creed which is required to justify a particular plan” (142). To that end, the winning faction will try to indoctrinate everyone else into accepting their code of values, especially the superiority of their supporters’ claims on redistribution.
Systems of social uniformity inaugurated by the collectivists in Germany and Italy, those of “of organizing sports and games, football and hiking, in party clubs where the members would not be infected by other views […] political uniforms and military party formations”—were quickly adopted by fascists and Nazis (143). Their support came from disenfranchised office workers, small tradesmen, and petty officials, “a new underprivileged class against the labor aristocracy which the industrial labor movement had created” (144).
Fascists and Nazis, along with their followers, “had no illusions about the capacity of reason to decide all the questions” (146). The revolt within the socialist classes would be won by the largest and toughest group.
When campaigning for increased economic security through government planning, progressives tend to ignore the costs to their freedom. It’s one thing for a society to provide “security against severe physical privation,” but quite another to try to guarantee for all “the security of a given standard of life” (147).
Hayek supports government efforts to provide against severe want, acts of God, and major economic downturns. He even approves of government social and medical insurance. He draws the line, however, at “that special kind of planning which according to its advocates is to replace the market,” or “public works undertaken on a very large scale,” which require the heavy hand of government in the marketplace (148).
What Hayek counsels against is the effort to insure that workers’ incomes do not fluctuate, as they do in a market economy. This effort leads to loss of freedom to choose one’s field of work: “When a person’s income is guaranteed, he can neither be allowed to stay in his job merely because he likes it nor to choose what other work he would like to do” (150). Likewise, workers who perform very well do not receive merit pay.
Since workers cannot easily be let go under forced full employment, their mistakes tend instead to be punished as crimes. They become like slave labor to be whipped, or like soldiers in a regimented, military society.
Each time a sheltered group receives a raise, the other groups will complain: “with every grant of complete security to one group the insecurity of the rest necessarily increases” (153). Prices and wages may remain stable, but production and employment gyrate up and down. Thus, “the more we try to provide full security by interfering with the market system, the greater the insecurity becomes” (154). Finally, “[i]t is no longer independence but security which gives rank and status” (154).
The nations of the West seem to be preparing their youth for a similar future: enterprise is denigrated, profit is a bad word, and capitalism is condemned as a great evil. The lesson to heed is Germany, where the spirit of enterprise slowly was stifled to the point that “so large a proportion of her people did not regard themselves as independent but as appointed functionaries” (155). Liberty becomes too expensive, and too risky.
Each of us is unique, unusual, and sometimes even eccentric. One of our tasks in life is to find employment that suits our individuality. That involves risk, to be sure, but the option even to try is lost under collectivism.
In a centrally-planned economy, where jobs are guaranteed and wages regulated, individual needs are set aside. The system must fulfill the overarching plan for fairness and equality, and personal quirks have to be sacrificed. Hayek deduces that the guarantee of work comes with the cost that the worker must toil where he or she is assigned.
Workers in a planned economy receive jobs allocated by bureaucrats, and must push and shove to get to the head of the line for their preferred work. Whom you know, instead of how good you are at your job, determines your success. There is no chance to create a career of your own. Someone smart but quirky might be assigned menial tasks at a lonely work station. The freedom to find one’s best livelihood is gone.
If security in a collectivist society is bought at the expense of personal satisfaction, so also is equality purchased at great cost. Visitors to the Soviet Union described an impoverished Russian socialist population that bicycled or rode crowded trollies from tiny, chilly apartments to the factories, while the ruling planners cruised by limo from luxury country estates to comfortable government offices. Most people were equal, if only in their poverty. The tragic irony was that a concentrated elite controlled vastly more power than widely-dispersed capitalists ever could. Collectivism did work, if only for the planners themselves.