58 pages • 1 hour read
Will DurantA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
Turning at last to his native United States, Durant finds that one America looks with fondness toward its European (especially English) forebears and sees their own country as an extension of its culture and traditions. The other America fiercely rejects such foreign influences, seeing America alone as a source worth cultivating and preferring the common sense of the average man to the refined wisdom of the continental aristocrat.
Turning first to George Santayana, a Spanish immigrant, Durant presents him as part of a dying breed of Europeanized American philosophers. A poet as well as a philosopher, Santayana came to prominence for his multivolume work The Life of Reason, after which he left the United States for England. In his work Skepticism and Animal Faith, Santayana describes “animal faith” as denoting beliefs which may not be correct, but which are nonetheless valuable in reflecting a universal and ineradicable human impulse. Everyone must rely on all manner of information beyond their sensory perception, or else life is simply impossible to manage.
There can in fact be a happy union between reason and instinct, with science providing “merely a shorthand description of regularities observed in our experience, rather than ‘laws’ governing the world and guaranteed unchangeable” (536). This is a suitable object of faith, but an incomplete one, as “the flower and its seed, the child and its laughter, contain more of the mystery of the universe than any machine that ever was on land or sea” (539). In that vein, he regards religion as a potentially beautiful expression of humanity’s innermost desires, even if he cannot bring himself into the camp of the faithful. He has no use for the iconoclasts who tear down religion for being untrue, preferring those who “leave undisturbed the myths that so comfort and inspire the life of the people; and perhaps he will a little envy them their hope” (544).
For Santayana, the great problem of philosophy was that an increasingly complex society required organizing principles which could not possibly have an objective existence, as anything beyond the family (and even that, to an extent) was what is now called a social construction. Democracy threatened to make matters far worse with its insistence on flattering the prejudices of the masses. Unlike Nietzsche, he does not yearn for a pre-democratic age, but does hope for a system that can find its wisest and most capable for its elected leaders.
William James is a more thoroughly American figure, the inventor of what has been called the most American of philosophic traditions, pragmatism. He was the brother of the novelist Henry James, who had a much greater European sensibility. Impatient with excessive abstractions, James’s pragmatism sought “truth as an objective relation, as once good and beauty had been; now what if truth, like these, were also relative to human judgment and human needs?” (557). Given the unknowability of natural law, the next best thing was to figure out which ideas were most beneficial to the individual, society, and humanity at large. An example is religious tolerance: It cannot be proven whether there is a god, but surely it is better for a society to tolerate a multitude of religious perspectives and their own version of the truth rather than insist upon the imposition of one (or none) upon the others. Pluralism also allows for multiple visions of the truth to interact with one another, producing new syntheses, whereas “a monistic world is for us a dead world” (561). James was quintessentially American in his desire to “cut through the cobwebs that had entangled philosophy” (565) and build a consensus on the foundations of common sense.
Finally, John Dewey made his mark as a philosopher of education. A devoted student of evolution with little regard for metaphysics, he tended to dismiss his philosophic forebears who did not share his commitment to naturalism as no better than medieval Scholastics. He fully embraced the modernist faith that “the problem of philosophy is not how we can come to know an external world, but how we can learn to control it and remake it” (569, emphasis added). This belief extended to the human person, whom Dewey regarded as almost entirely malleable, especially at a young age, given how much of life is socially constructed. It is incumbent upon adults to change what they think they know about the world to prepare children for a new and better world.
It is on this basis that Dewey accepts democracy—a rare quality among philosophers—both because he believes “the aim of a political order is to help the individual to develop himself completely” (572) and because of his confidence that the public at large can one day internalize the wisdom normally reserved for a philosophic elite. Should such internalization succeed, then philosophers would be kings, and everyone would be a king.
Pertaining only to the previous chapter, the Conclusion notes that Santayana is by far the most significant philosopher, and the one with the most European sensibilities. Durant finds that the United States has not yet developed a philosophical tradition of its own, which is not a criticism: Europe took many centuries to develop its own, and lost it for centuries before recovering it.
However, Durant worries that the current state of the United States is filled with what he calls “our own superficiality, our provincialism, our narrowness and our bigotry, our immature intolerance and our timid violence against innovation and experiment” (576), which makes the prospect of philosophical flowering seem distant. For now, Americans are too pragmatic for philosophy, but having used the practical arts to accrue wealth, wealth now has the possibility to create luxury, which in turn opens the possibility of art. With the nation entering “puberty” (577), it can anticipate a period of maturity and intellectual development.
As Durant often points out, philosophy is an elite activity, and the majority of its practitioners have frowned on democracy. Santayana, whom Durant clearly regards as the United States’ greatest philosopher—he explicitly attributes part of his greatness to not being a native-born American—was skeptical of democracy, musing nostalgically, “was there not more happiness for men in the old aristocratic doctrine that the good is not liberty, but wisdom, and contentment with one’s natural restrictions[?]” and adding, “the classical tradition knew that only a few can win” (549). Santayana’s belief in the importance of wisdom above all, and his hope that the wisest can become elected leaders, carries echoes of Plato’s desire for philosopher kings. Meanwhile, his attempts to unify reason and instinct and his indulgence toward religious faith speak once more to a countercurrent in 20th-century philosophy against the rigid materialism of the preceding century.
The staunchly pro-democratic philosophy of James and Dewey is concerned almost exclusively with practical and social goals rather than abstract or metaphysical inquiry into The Nature of Human Beings and the World. Democracy is ultimately based on the premise that all people have an equal right of participation in the making of the laws, and if the traditional philosophical response has been that people are not of equal talent and wisdom, then Dewey’s reply is to bestow them with such talent and wisdom through comprehensive public education. Democracy must likewise bend its standards to fit majority tastes, and so James introduces a democratic concept of truth as whatever is “expedient in the long run and on the whole” (557) for the common good. A democratic society may not come up with the most refined ideas, he argues, but it is often far more effective than its aristocratic forbearers in developing a system of thought suited to the needs and interests of its own social structure.
Appearance Versus Reality
View Collection
Beauty
View Collection
Community
View Collection
Good & Evil
View Collection
Inspiring Biographies
View Collection
Philosophy, Logic, & Ethics
View Collection
Psychology
View Collection
Science & Nature
View Collection
Trust & Doubt
View Collection
Truth & Lies
View Collection