logo

58 pages 1 hour read

Will Durant

The Story of Philosophy: The Lives and Opinions of the Greater Philosophers

Nonfiction | Reference/Text Book | Adult | Published in 1926

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Chapter 4Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Chapter 4 Summary: “Spinoza”

Spinoza is the only Jewish member of Durant’s pantheon (except for a brief treatment of Henri Bergson), and so the chapter begins with a brief overview of the Jewish experience, one of dispersion and persecution across many centuries. Jewish philosophy flowered in Muslim-dominated Spain, and then went into decline falling the expulsion of Spanish Jews in 1492. Some of the exiled fled to Holland and built a flourishing community which produced Baruch (also known as Benedictus) Spinoza.

Spinoza followed his synagogue education with training in Latin and European philosophy, admiring Descartes’s “desire to explain all of the world except God and the soul by mechanical and mathematical law” (167). His philosophizing led to his excommunication, with the Jews of Holland eager to assure the Christian masters in the middle of their own religious wars that they would not have one more front of heresy to confront.

After surviving an assassination attempt, he adopted the name Benedict, lived with several Christian patrons, and produced most of his writings, only a few of which he published during his lifetime. Despite his relative seclusion and modest means, he gained enough fame to win a pension from King Louis XIV after French forces defeated the Dutch in 1672. He rejected the pension because of his refusal to uphold the Catholic pieties of the French state. He died shortly afterward at the age of 44.

Spinoza’s Theologico-Political Treatise offers the then-extremely controversial argument that the Bible is not a literally factual account, instead reflecting a specific cultural origin rather than universal truth for all humanity. The Bible also separates the workings of nature from the intervention of God—which Spinoza believes are one and the same (180)—because people wanted to believe that God was acting specially for them, and not simply according to fixed laws that operate the same way for everyone.

Spinoza argues that the Bible still has great moral value, but he wants to isolate its moral teaching from the doctrinal strife common in his day. For example, seeing Jesus as a great teacher, rather than the Son of God, would allow Christians and Jews to unite over him rather than fight over who earns his divine inheritance. This striking departure from Christian doctrine is part of Spinoza’s project of achieving happiness through complete intellectual freedom. To achieve intellectual freedom, one must have a proper sense of which elements constitute knowledge and the value of each, with intuition at the lower end and reason informed by perception at the higher, especially when reason identifies eternal rather than transient truths.

Spinoza’s greatest contribution is his Ethics, a subject he approaches with mathematical rigor, making the book as dense as a book of mathematical equations. It begins with metaphysics, defining the terms “substance, attribute and mode” (187). A mode “is any individual thing or event” that finds itself within reality at a given place and time, while substance is “that which eternally and unchangeably is, and of which everything else must be a transient form or mode” (188). Substance relates to nature and God (which, again, Spinoza considers jointly), and so every action indicates the operation of natural laws. Humans criticize nature with terms like “evil” only because they lack full knowledge of nature and its underlying mechanics.

Nature encapsulates all of mind and matter, and all of existence thereby exhibits the duality between these two processes, which are intricately connected but incapable of seeing the fullness of the other’s reality. Spinoza settles on the admittedly artificial distinction of intellect, “an abstract and short-hand term for a series of ideas,” and will, “an abstract term for a series of actions or volitions” (194-95). Intellect can conceive of anything, but will is required to render it into action, and so will, or desire, becomes central to all human action. Humans are gratified when they achieve what they will, and feel pain when they fail to acquire it, or receive what they do not will. In this regard, humans are no less mechanical than any other aspect of nature.

What is ethical is therefore what brings pleasure, and what is pleasurable tends to involve the preservation or other benefit of the self. In contradiction to Christian ethics, Spinoza regards nothing wrong with “an inevitable and justifiable egoism” (199). This is healthiest when the desires of the mind learn to restrain the desires that merely belong to the body. A refined reason will show a person what will truly make them happy, rather than place them at the mercy of successive, fleeting passions.

Humans may not be free in a metaphysical sense, but determinism also points the way toward a fulfilling life. Notably, this does not require God in a Christian sense, as “[b]lessedness [divine favor] is not the reward of virtue, but virtue itself” (207). The goal of the state is to promote such virtue, which in turn depends on a measure of individual freedom. From Spinoza, we therefore see the earliest signs of what would later be called political liberalism.

Chapter 4 Analysis

Durant once more addresses The Sociohistorical Context of Philosophy by presenting Spinoza as an innovative thinker who faced staunch resistance from most of his contemporaries. Spinoza’s life and thought show how many of the assumptions at the heart of liberal theory—individual rights, religious toleration, and social progress—once stood in stark contrast to the prevailing ethos of European society, and would require centuries to weave themselves into the mainstream.

The transition from a Christian culture to a liberal one began with a Jewish philosopher whose family was only a few generations removed from vicious persecution in Spain. To make matters worse, Spinoza alienated himself from the Jewish community, and had to spend the rest of his relatively short life in a state of physical and social precarity. His reliance on Christian patrons could easily have induced him to moderation and caution, but instead Spinoza authored some of the most controversial opinions of his time.

In many cases, Spinoza’s opinions would still be controversial in some theological traditions today, such as the idea that the Bible cannot and should not be read as literal truth or his assertion that Christians should reject the idea of Jesus as divine. In addressing The Nature of Human Beings and the World, Spinoza offered a purely rational and systematic approach, arguing that, since God and nature are the same, there is no such thing as God intervening through natural forces to display support or displeasure in human affairs (e.g., natural disasters as a punishment for sin). Spinoza’s attitude once more reflects the gradual break with the medieval scholastic tradition, as medieval thinkers tended to interpret all natural phenomena and major events as intimately tied to God’s will and personal intervention. Like Bacon, Spinoza suggests that the best way of understanding the world is to take a more empirical approach, studying the laws of how nature and life function instead of deriving knowledge through divine revelation.

Another one of Spinoza’s most significant contributions is his tendency to regard all of existence as a function of an external nature, raising the theme of Science, Morality, and Free Will. The ancient Greeks talked extensively of nature, but especially regarding human beings, treated it as something they could shape or enter through training. Spinoza argued that “there is […] no free will: the necessities of survival determine instinct, instinct determines desire, and desire determines thought and action” (196). Spinoza thus leaves his modern readers with a great paradox: He is a major forerunner of liberalism, the great theory of political liberty, and yet in a cosmic sense, he regards human beings as having no liberty whatsoever. On the question of Science, Morality, and Free Will, he unites the first two at the expense of the third.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text