logo

56 pages 1 hour read

Michael J. Sandel

What Money Can’t Buy: The Moral Limits of Markets

Nonfiction | Book | Adult | Published in 2012

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Chapter 3Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Chapter 3: “How Markets Crowd Out Morals”

Chapter 3, Section 1 Summary: “What Money Can and Cannot Buy”

Sandel states that there are some things that money self-evidently should not buy, like friends or the Nobel Prize. The good of these things is negated by the fact that they are purchased.

On the other hand, some things can be bought without their inherent worth being affected, but shouldn’t. Some suggest that a market for babies would create more efficiency in enabling adoption than adoption agencies, but most believe that this is ethically immoral.

Chapter 3, Section 2 Summary: “Bought Apologies and Wedding Toasts”

A Japanese company hires out articulate individuals to deliver apologies. An online company ghostwrites wedding speeches for individuals. These things become less meaningful if they are outsourced and paid for.

Chapter 3, Section 3 Summary: “The Case Against Gifts”

Gifts are inefficient from an economic perspective, as the gift receiver usually has a more accurate idea of what they want than the gift giver. The fact that there is a social taboo against giving cash reveals the fact that gifts are meant as a luxury, rather than utilitarian, item.

Chapter 3, Section 4 Summary: “Monetizing Gifts”

Gift cards are a halfway point between money, which allows the receiver choice, and a gift, which shows knowledge of the person, as the element of choosing an appropriate store allows the buyer to convey their knowledge of the gift receiver.

Chapter 3, Section 5 Summary: “Bought Honor”

Honorary degrees are sometimes conferred on people who have not studied at an institution. In some cases, they are awarded to individuals for making donations to the establishment.

Although most university places are merit-based, there are some cases where admission might be mediated by a donation as well as by academic merit, sporting ability, parents’ alumni status, and a range of other factors; it is usually difficult to ascertain to what extent donations played a part.

Chapter 3, Section 6 Summary: “Two Objections to Markets”

The first objection to market-based choices is that they perpetuate wealth inequality. The second issue is that the corrupt nature of making financially-savvy choices may corrode the integrity of an institution’s norms.

The market suggests that fairness is achieved by allowing people what they want to buy and sell, but some choices aren’t freely made.

Chapter 3, Section 7 Summary: “Crowding out Nonmarket Norms”

Markets can touch or taint the goods they touch, changing the inherent value of that thing. Furthermore, as is illustrated in earlier chapters, sometimes paying for a thing, such as a behavior, decreases rather than increases that behavior, such as paying children to read resulting in less intrinsic motivation and, therefore, less reading in the long term.

Chapter 3, Section 8 Summary: “Nuclear Waste Sites”

Swiss residents, who reluctantly accepted having a nuclear waste dump near their town out of a sense of civic duty, become more reluctant when offered an annual cash incentive from the government in return for the proximity of the nuclear waste dump. They felt uncomfortable with being bribed; the addition of the financial incentive crowded out the sense of civic duty.

Civic sacrifice repaid through public works or projects is accepted more readily, contradicting pragmatic economists who suggest that cash would always be better than a gift.

Chapter 3, Section 9 Summary: “Donation Day and Late Pickups”

Three groups of Israeli students were sent door to door to collect money for charitable causes. The group offered no remuneration for their collections earned the most for the charities, whereas the groups offered financial incentives collected less, although the group offered 10% or their revenue did better than those offered 1%. Paying the students changed the nature of the activity for them; it was an activity motivated by personal gain, rather than by civic duty.

Chapter 3, Section 10 Summary: “The Commercialization Effect”

Fred Hirsch, a British economist, suggested “the commercialization effect,” whereby the product is affected by its commercialization, rather than if it were distributed via feelings of service, love, altruism, or in an informal exchange.

Lawyers asked to give retired people legal services for a reduced fee ($30 an hour) refused, but accepted when they were asked to do it for free as a charitable service.

People’s intrinsic motivation is “crowded-out” by extrinsic motivation when services or goods are monetized, which changes their relationship to the good or service. This is an important anomaly in economics, as usually increasing financial incentives increases supply.

Chapter 3, Section 11 Summary: “Blood for Sale”

British sociologist Richard Titmuss, in 1970, comparatively examined the British and American blood bank systems: Britain relied on charitable donations, whereas America offered money for blood donations. Britain attained greater supplies of blood, proving that charitable donations made greater sense from a pragmatic, economic perspective. Furthermore, Titmuss also pointed out the moral implications, as blood donations were supplied primarily from the poor in America. Charitable donors thus were “crowded-out” in the American system.

Chapter 3, Section 12 Summary: “Two Tenets of Market Faith”

A core tenet of market principles is that commercializing an activity doesn’t change it: People could choose to participate in a market for a product or service, or not if it contradicts their values around that subject. However, the blood donation and selling example illustrates that commercializing blood changes the meaning of donating it.

The second tenet is that altruism is a finite resource that should be used sparingly; therefore, one should rely on markets wherever possible.

Chapter 3, Section 13 Summary: “Economizing Love”

Sir Dennis H. Robertson, an economist, suggested that love is a scarce resource that should be used sparingly. However, on the other hand, love could be viewed as expansive—it enlarges with practice.

Economist Lawrence Summers aligned himself with Robertson, suggesting that boycotting sweatshops is unproductive, as markets should be run on commercial principles and altruism should be spared for individuals’ personal lives.

Sandel counters both economists, suggesting that altruism in public life is sorely missing, and that “altruism, generosity, solidarity, and civic spirit are not like commodities that are depleted with use” (158). 

Chapter 3 Analysis

Sandel argues against the economic principles that suggest that financial incentives will increase supply and that there are no undesirable consequences to this increase. Instead, Sandel continues to stress The Immorality of Over-Commodification. This immorality takes place on two levels: a lack of fairness, and the introduction of corruption.

In terms of fairness, market values are justified through the lens that participation is voluntary. Creating a market for blood is proposed as unproblematic based on this reasoning, as people who do not agree can opt out. However, Sandel refers to Titmuss’s findings, which concluded that in the commercialized United States blood industry, low socio-economic groups—primarily from African American neighborhoods and from within prisons—were by far the biggest donors. Thus, participation was clearly not entirely voluntary, but coerced through poverty: “[A] new class is emerging of an exploited human population of high blood yielders” (149), reflecting the links between Free-Market Values and Social Inequality. Sandel suggests that supporters of free-market values ignore the inconvenient truth that we are not bargaining on fair and equal terms: “[S]uch choices are not truly voluntary. Market choices are not free choices if some people are desperately poor or lack the ability to bargain on fair terms” (135, emphasis added).

Sandel also explores this inequity in terms of the increasing trend of financial donations of students’ families being a factor in university admissions. Sandel objects to the practice of commercializing a selection process that ought to be based on merit: “[A]dmitting children of wealthy donors in exchange for a handsome donation to the college fund is unfair to applicants who lacked the good judgment to be born to affluent parents” (132). In an instance of satire, Sandel accuses the applicants born to modest households of lacking the “good judgment” to belong to wealthy families; through paralipsis, he points out that children have no choice in their family of origin, and therefore that this should never be a factor in selection, as “giving an edge to children of the wealthy perpetuates social and economic inequality” (132).

Sandel also examines the corruption of values that occurs with increasing commercialization, once more invoking The Immorality of Over-Commodification. In Titmuss’s blood study, “once people begin to view blood as a commodity that is routinely bought and sold they are less likely to feel a moral responsibility to donate it” (150, emphasis added). Sandel explores the idea that commercializing markets has “a corrosive effect on the norm of giving” (151). The economic principle whereby intrinsic motivation is “crowded-out” by extrinsic motivation (i.e., being paid) supports Sandel’s thesis that commodification corrodes important social value systems, such as civic goodness and altruism. This is apparent in the Swiss town feeling less inclined to support the nuclear waste plant when they were incentivized, as well as the lawyers preferring to give free advice to pensioners rather than for a dramatically reduced fee. In both cases, “the intrusion of market norms crowded out their sense of civic duty” (140, emphasis added).

Sandel therefore stresses that, contrary to traditional market theory, “when people are engaged in an activity they consider intrinsically worthwhile, offering them money may weaken their motivation by depreciating or ‘crowding out’ their intrinsic interest or commitment” (147). Through proving that marketizing goods impacts individuals’ relationship to that good, Sandel continues to stress The Importance of Debate on Market Values, arguing that people should understand the corrosive impact of market values in order to decide at what point these values should be limited from entering traditionally nonmarket spheres.

Sandel’s findings reach into the spheres of social values and morality. He argues, through exploring the “crowding-out phenomenon,” that modern markets displace vitally important and inherently human characteristics, such as “altruism, generosity, solidarity, and civic spirit” (158). Sandel uses the analogy of muscles to illustrate the fact that applying these values to public life will enhance rather than deplete them, and that we should ensure that these values are not lost in favor of an increasingly commercialized world that values profitable markets above the common good.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text